home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
- --------
- No. 90-7675
- --------
- R. A. V., PETITIONER v. CITY OF
- ST. PAUL, MINNESOTA
- on writ of certiorari to the supreme court of
- minnesota
- [June 22, 1992]
-
- Justice White, with whom Justice Blackmun and
- Justice O'Connor join, and with whom Justice Stevens
- joins except as to Part I(A), concurring in the judgment.
- I agree with the majority that the judgment of the
- Minnesota Supreme Court should be reversed. However,
- our agreement ends there.
- This case could easily be decided within the contours of
- established First Amendment law by holding, as petitioner
- argues, that the St. Paul ordinance is fatally overbroad
- because it criminalizes not only unprotected expression but
- expression protected by the First Amendment. See Part II,
- infra. Instead, -find[ing] it unnecessary- to consider the
- questions upon which we granted review, ante, at 3, the
- Court holds the ordinance facially unconstitutional on a
- ground that was never presented to the Minnesota Supreme
- Court, a ground that has not been briefed by the parties
- before this Court, a ground that requires serious departures
- from the teaching of prior cases and is inconsistent with the
- plurality opinion in Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. ---
- (1992), which was joined by two of the five Justices in the
- majority in the present case.
- This Court ordinarily is not so eager to abandon its
- precedents. Twice within the past month, the Court has
- declined to overturn longstanding but controversial deci-
- sions on questions of constitutional law. See Allied Signal,
- Inc. v. Director, Division of Taxation, 504 U. S. - (1992);
- Quill Corp. v. North Dakota, 504 U. S. - (1992). In each
- case, we had the benefit of full briefing on the critical issue,
- so that the parties and amici had the opportunity to apprise
- us of the impact of a change in the law. And in each case,
- the Court declined to abandon its precedents, invoking the
- principle of stare decisis. Allied Signal, Inc., supra, at -
- (slip op., at 12); Quill Corp., supra, at - (slip op., at
- 17-18).
- But in the present case, the majority casts aside long-
- established First Amendment doctrine without the benefit
- of briefing and adopts an untried theory. This is hardly a
- judicious way of proceeding, and the Court's reasoning in
- reaching its result is transparently wrong.
- I
- A
- This Court's decisions have plainly stated that expression
- falling within certain limited categories so lacks the values
- the First Amendment was designed to protect that the
- Constitution affords no protection to that expression.
- Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 (1942), made
- the point in the clearest possible terms:
- -There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited
- classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of
- which have never been thought to raise any Constitu-
- tional problem. . . . It has been well observed that such
- utterances are no essential part of any exposition of
- ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step to
- truth that any benefit that may be derived from them
- is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
- morality.- Id., at 571-572.
- See also Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States,
- Inc., 466 U. S. 485, 504 (1984) (citing Chaplinsky).
- Thus, as the majority concedes, see ante, at 5, this Court
- has long held certain discrete categories of expression to be
- proscribable on the basis of their content. For instance, the
- Court has held that the individual who falsely shouts -fire-
- in a crowded theatre may not claim the protection of the
- First Amendment. Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S. 47,
- 52 (1919). The Court has concluded that neither child
- pornography, nor obscenity, is protected by the First
- Amendment. New York v. Ferber, 458 U. S. 747, 764
- (1982); Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15, 20 (1973); Roth v.
- United States, 354 U. S. 476, 484-485 (1957). And the
- Court has observed that, -[l]eaving aside the special
- considerations when public officials [and public figures] are
- the target, a libelous publication is not protected by the
- Constitution.- Ferber, supra, at 763 (citations omitted).
- All of these categories are content based. But the Court
- has held that First Amendment does not apply to them
- because their expressive content is worthless or of de
- minimis value to society. Chaplinsky, supra, at 571-572.
- We have not departed from this principle, emphasizing
- repeatedly that, -within the confines of [these] given
- classification[s], the evil to be restricted so overwhelmingly
- outweighs the expressive interests, if any, at stake, that no
- process of case-by-case adjudication is required.- Ferber,
- supra, at 763-764; Bigelow v. Virginia, 421 U. S. 809, 819
- (1975). This categorical approach has provided a principled
- and narrowly focused means for distinguishing between
- expression that the government may regulate freely and
- that which it may regulate on the basis of content only
- upon a showing of compelling need.
-
- Today, however, the Court announces that earlier Courts
- did not mean their repeated statements that certain
- categories of expression are -not within the area of constitu-
- tionally protected speech.- Roth, supra, at 483. See ante,
- at 5, citing Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250, 266
- (1952); Chaplinsky, supra, at 571-572; Bose Corp., supra, at
- 504; Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S.
- 115, 124 (1989). The present Court submits that such clear
- statements -must be taken in context- and are not -literally
- true.- Ante, at 5.
- To the contrary, those statements meant precisely what
- they said: The categorical approach is a firmly entrenched
- part of our First Amendment jurisprudence. Indeed, the
- Court in Roth reviewed the guarantees of freedom of
- expression in effect at the time of the ratification of the
- Constitution and concluded, -[i]n light of this history, it is
- apparent that the unconditional phrasing of the First
- Amendment was not intended to protect every utterance.-
- 354 U. S., at 482-483.
- In its decision today, the Court points to -[n]othing . . . in
- this Court's precedents warrant[ing] disregard of this
- longstanding tradition.- Burson, 504 U. S., at --- (slip op.,
- at 3) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment); Allied Signal,
- Inc., supra, at --- (slip op., at 12). Nevertheless, the
- majority holds that the First Amendment protects those
- narrow categories of expression long held to be undeserving
- of First Amendment protection-at least to the extent that
- lawmakers may not regulate some fighting words more
- strictly than others because of their content. The Court
- announces that such content-based distinctions violate the
- First Amendment because -the government may not
- regulate use based on hostility-or favoritism-towards the
- underlying message expressed.- Ante, at 8. Should the
- government want to criminalize certain fighting words, the
- Court now requires it to criminalize all fighting words.
- To borrow a phrase, -Such a simplistic, all-or-nothing-at-
- all approach to First Amendment protection is at odds with
- common sense and with our jurisprudence as well.- Ante,
- at 6. It is inconsistent to hold that the government may
- proscribe an entire category of speech because the content
- of that speech is evil, Ferber, supra, at 763-764; but that
- the government may not treat a subset of that category
- differently without violating the First Amendment; the
- content of the subset is by definition worthless and unde-
- serving of constitutional protection.
- The majority's observation that fighting words are ``quite
- expressive indeed,'' ante, at 7, is no answer. Fighting words
- are not a means of exchanging views, rallying supporters,
- or registering a protest; they are directed against individu-
- als to provoke violence or to inflict injury. Chaplinsky, 315
- U. S., at 572. Therefore, a ban on all fighting words or on
- a subset of the fighting words category would restrict only
- the social evil of hate speech, without creating the danger
- of driving viewpoints from the marketplace. See ante, at 9.
- Therefore, the Court's insistence on inventing its brand
- of First Amendment underinclusiveness puzzles me. The
- overbreadth doctrine has the redeeming virtue of attempt-
- ing to avoid the chilling of protected expression, Broadrick
- v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601, 612 (1973); Osborne v. Ohio,
- 495 U. S. 103, 112, n. 8 (1990); Brockett v. Spokane Arcades,
- Inc., 472 U. S. 491, 503 (1985); Ferber, supra, at 772, but
- the Court's new -underbreadth- creation serves no desirable
- function. Instead, it permits, indeed invites, the continua-
- tion of expressive conduct that in this case is evil and
- worthless in First Amendment terms, see Ferber, supra, at
- 763-764; Chaplinsky, supra, at 571-572, until the city of St.
- Paul cures the underbreadth by adding to its ordinance a
- catch-all phrase such as -and all other fighting words that
- may constitutionally be subject to this ordinance.-
- Any contribution of this holding to First Amendment
- jurisprudence is surely a negative one, since it necessarily
- signals that expressions of violence, such as the message of
- intimidation and racial hatred conveyed by burning a cross
- on someone's lawn, are of sufficient value to outweigh the
- social interest in order and morality that has traditionally
- placed such fighting words outside the First Amendment.
- Indeed, by characterizing fighting words as a form of
- `'debate,'' ante, at 13, the majority legitimates hate speech
- as a form of public discussion.
- Furthermore, the Court obscures the line between speech
- that could be regulated freely on the basis of content (i.e.,
- the narrow categories of expression falling outside the First
- Amendment) and that which could be regulated on the
- basis of content only upon a showing of a compelling state
- interest (i.e., all remaining expression). By placing fighting
- words, which the Court has long held to be valueless, on at
- least equal constitutional footing with political discourse
- and other forms of speech that we have deemed to have the
- greatest social value, the majority devalues the latter
- category. See Burson v. Freeman, supra, at --- (slip op., at
- 4-5); Eu v. San Francisco County Democratic Central
- Comm., 489 U. S. 214, 222-223 (1989).
- B
- In a second break with precedent, the Court refuses to
- sustain the ordinance even though it would survive under
- the strict scrutiny applicable to other protected expression.
- Assuming, arguendo, that the St. Paul ordinance is a
- content-based regulation of protected expression, it never-
- theless would pass First Amendment review under settled
- law upon a showing that the regulation -`is necessary to
- serve a compelling state interest and is narrowly drawn to
- achieve that end.'- Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. New York
- Crime Victims Board, 502 U. S. ---, --- (1991) (slip op., at
- 11) (quoting Arkansas Writers' Project, Inc., v. Ragland, 481
- U. S. 221, 231 (1987)). St. Paul has urged that its ordi-
- nance, in the words of the majority, -helps to ensure the
- basic human rights of members of groups that have
- historically been subjected to discrimination . . . .- Ante, at
- 17. The Court expressly concedes that this interest is
- compelling and is promoted by the ordinance. Ibid.
- Nevertheless, the Court treats strict scrutiny analysis as
- irrelevant to the constitutionality of the legislation:
- -The dispositive question . . . is whether content
- discrimination is reasonably necessary in order to
- achieve St. Paul's compelling interests; it plainly is not.
- An ordinance not limited to the favored topics would
- have precisely the same beneficial effect.- Ibid.
- Under the majority's view, a narrowly drawn, content-based
- ordinance could never pass constitutional muster if the
- object of that legislation could be accomplished by banning
- a wider category of speech. This appears to be a general
- renunciation of strict scrutiny review, a fundamental tool of
- First Amendment analysis.
- This abandonment of the doctrine is inexplicable in light
- of our decision in Burson v. Freeman, supra, which was
- handed down just a month ago. In Burson, seven of the
- eight participating members of the Court agreed that the
- strict scrutiny standard applied in a case involving a First
- Amendment challenge to a content-based statute. See id.,
- at ___ (slip op., at 6) (plurality); id., at --- (slip op., at 1)
- (Stevens, J., dissenting). The statute at issue prohibited
- the solicitation of votes and the display or distribution of
- campaign materials within 100 feet of the entrance to a
- polling place. The plurality concluded that the legislation
- survived strict scrutiny because the State had asserted a
- compelling interest in regulating electioneering near polling
- places and because the statute at issue was narrowly
- tailored to accomplish that goal. Id., at --- (slip op., at
- 17-18).
- Significantly, the statute in Burson did not proscribe all
- speech near polling places; it restricted only political
- speech. Id., at --- (slip op., at 5). The Burson plurality,
- which included The Chief Justice and Justice Kennedy,
- concluded that the distinction between types of speech
- required application of strict scrutiny, but it squarely
- rejected the proposition that the legislation failed First
- Amendment review because it could have been drafted in
- broader, content-neutral terms:
- -States adopt laws to address the problems that con-
- front them. The First Amendment does not require
- States to regulate for problems that do not exist.- Id.,
- at --- (slip op., at 16) (emphasis added).
- This reasoning is in direct conflict with the majority's
- analysis in the present case, which leaves two options to
- lawmakers attempting to regulate expressions of violence:
- (1) enact a sweeping prohibition on an entire class of speech
- (thereby requiring -regulat[ion] for problems that do not
- exist); or (2) not legislate at all.
- Had the analysis adopted by the majority in the present
- case been applied in Burson, the challenged election law
- would have failed constitutional review, for its content-
- based distinction between political and nonpolitical speech
- could not have been characterized as -reasonably neces-
- sary,- ante, at 17, to achieve the State's interest in regulat-
- ing polling place premises.
- As with its rejection of the Court's categorical analysis,
- the majority offers no reasoned basis for discarding our
- firmly established strict scrutiny analysis at this time. The
- majority appears to believe that its doctrinal revisionism is
- necessary to prevent our elected lawmakers from prohibit-
- ing libel against members of one political party but not
- another and from enacting similarly preposterous laws.
- Ante, at 5-6. The majority is misguided.
- Although the First Amendment does not apply to catego-
- ries of unprotected speech, such as fighting words, the
- Equal Protection Clause requires that the regulation of
- unprotected speech be rationally related to a legitimate
- government interest. A defamation statute that drew
- distinctions on the basis of political affiliation or -an
- ordinance prohibiting only those legally obscene works that
- contain criticism of the city government,- ante, at 6, would
- unquestionably fail rational basis review.
- Turning to the St. Paul ordinance and assuming arguen-
- do, as the majority does, that the ordinance is not constitu-
- tionally overbroad (but see Part II, infra), there is no
- question that it would pass equal protection review. The
- ordinance proscribes a subset of -fighting words,- those that
- injure -on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender.-
- This selective regulation reflects the City's judgment that
- harms based on race, color, creed, religion, or gender are
- more pressing public concerns than the harms caused by
- other fighting words. In light of our Nation's long and
- painful experience with discrimination, this determination
- is plainly reasonable. Indeed, as the majority concedes, the
- interest is compelling. Ante, at 17.
- C
- The Court has patched up its argument with an appar-
- ently nonexhaustive list of ad hoc exceptions, in what can
- be viewed either as an attempt to confine the effects of its
- decision to the facts of this case, see post, at --- (slip op.,
- at 1-2) (Blackmun, J., concurring in judgment), or as an
- effort to anticipate some of the questions that will arise
- from its radical revision of First Amendment law.
- For instance, if the majority were to give general applica-
- tion to the rule on which it decides this case, today's
- decision would call into question the constitutionality of the
- statute making it illegal to threaten the life of the Presi-
- dent. 18 U. S. C. 871. See Watts v. United States, 394
- U. S. 705 (1969) (per curiam). Surely, this statute, by
- singling out certain threats, incorporates a content-based
- distinction; it indicates that the Government especially
- disfavors threats against the President as opposed to
- threats against all others. See ante, at 13. But because
- the Government could prohibit all threats and not just
- those directed against the President, under the Court's
- theory, the compelling reasons justifying the enactment of
- special legislation to safeguard the President would be
- irrelevant, and the statute would fail First Amendment
- review.
- To save the statute, the majority has engrafted the
- following exception onto its newly announced First Amend-
- ment rule: Content-based distinctions may be drawn within
- an unprotected category of speech if the basis for the
- distinctions is ``the very reason the entire class of speech at
- issue is proscribable.'' Ante, at 9. Thus, the argument goes,
- the statute making it illegal to threaten the life of the
- President is constitutional, ``since the reasons why threats
- of violence are outside the First Amendment (protecting
- individuals from the fear of violence, from the disruption
- that fear engenders, and from the possibility that the
- threatened violence will occur) have special force when
- applied to the person of the President.'' Ante, at 10.
- The exception swallows the majority's rule. Certainly, it
- should apply to the St. Paul ordinance, since ``the reasons
- why [fighting words] are outside the First Amendment . . .
- have special force when applied to [groups that have
- historically been subjected to discrimination].''
- To avoid the result of its own analysis, the Court suggests
- that fighting words are simply a mode of communication,
- rather than a content-based category, and that the St. Paul
- ordinance has not singled out a particularly objectionable
- mode of communication. Ante, at 8, 15. Again, the majority
- confuses the issue. A prohibition on fighting words is not
- a time, place, or manner restriction; it is a ban on a class of
- speech that conveys an overriding message of personal
- injury and imminent violence, Chaplinsky, supra, at 572, a
- message that is at its ugliest when directed against groups
- that have long been the targets of discrimination. Accord-
- ingly, the ordinance falls within the first exception to the
- majority's theory.
- As its second exception, the Court posits that certain
- content-based regulations will survive under the new
- regime if the regulated subclass ``happens to be associated
- with particular `secondary effects' of the speech . . .,'' ante,
- at 10, which the majority treats as encompassing instances
- in which ``words can . . . violate laws directed not against
- speech but against conduct . . .'' Ante, at 11. Again,
- there is a simple explanation for the Court's eagerness to
- craft an exception to its new First Amendment rule: Under
- the general rule the Court applies in this case, Title VII
- hostile work environment claims would suddenly be
- unconstitutional.
- Title VII makes it unlawful to discriminate -because of
- [an] individual's race, color, religion, sex, or national
- origin,- 42 U. S. C. 2000e-2(a)(1), and the regulations
- covering hostile workplace claims forbid -sexual harass-
- ment,- which includes -[u]nwelcome sexual advances,
- requests for sexual favors, and other verbal or physical
- conduct of a sexual nature- which creates -an intimidating,
- hostile, or offensive working environment.- 29 CFR
- 1604.11(a) (1991). The regulation does not prohibit
- workplace harassment generally; it focuses on what the
- majority would characterize as the -disfavored topi[c]- of
- sexual harassment. Ante, at 13. In this way, Title VII is
- similar to the St. Paul ordinance that the majority con-
- demns because it -impose[s] special prohibitions on those
- speakers who express views on disfavored subjects.- Ibid.
- Under the broad principle the Court uses to decide the
- present case, hostile work environment claims based on
- sexual harassment should fail First Amendment review;
- because a general ban on harassment in the workplace
- would cover the problem of sexual harassment, any attempt
- to proscribe the subcategory of sexually harassing expres-
- sion would violate the First Amendment.
- Hence, the majority's second exception, which the Court
- indicates would insulate a Title VII hostile work environ-
- ment claim from an underinclusiveness challenge because
- ``sexually derogatory `fighting words'. . . may produce a
- violation of Title VII's general prohibition against sexual
- discrimination in employment practices.'' Ante, at 11. But
- application of this exception to a hostile work environment
- claim does not hold up under close examination.
- First, the hostile work environment regulation is not
- keyed to the presence or absence of an economic quid pro
- quo, Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson, 477 U. S. 57, 65
- (1986), but to the impact of the speech on the victimized
- worker. Consequently, the regulation would no more fall
- within a secondary effects exception than does the St. Paul
- ordinance. Ante, at 15-16. Second, the majority's focus on
- the statute's general prohibition on discrimination glosses
- over the language of the specific regulation governing
- hostile working environment, which reaches beyond any
- ``incidental'' effect on speech. United States v. O'Brien, 391
- U. S. 367, 376 (1968). If the relationship between the
- broader statute and specific regulation is sufficent to bring
- the Title VII regulation within O'Brien, then all St. Paul
- need do to bring its ordinance within this exception is to
- add some prefatory language concerning discrimination
- generally.
- As the third exception to the Court's theory for deciding
- this case, the majority concocts a catchall exclusion to
- protect against unforeseen problems, a concern that is
- heightened here given the lack of briefing on the majority's
- decisional theory. This final exception would apply in cases
- in which ``there is no realistic possibility that official
- suppression of ideas is afoot.'' Ante, at 12. As I have
- demonstrated, this case does not concern the official
- suppression of ideas. See supra, at 6. The majority
- discards this notion out-of-hand. Ante, at 16.
- As I see it, the Court's theory does not work and will do
- nothing more than confuse the law. Its selection of this
- case to rewrite First Amendment law is particularly
- inexplicable, because the whole problem could have been
- avoided by deciding this case under settled First Amend-
- ment principles.
-
-
- II
- Although I disagree with the Court's analysis, I do agree
- with its conclusion: The St. Paul ordinance is unconstitu-
- tional. However, I would decide the case on overbreadth
- grounds.
- We have emphasized time and again that overbreadth
- doctrine is an exception to the established principle that -a
- person to whom a statute may constitutionally be applied
- will not be heard to challenge that statute on the ground
- that it may conceivably be applied unconstitutionally to
- others, in other situations not before the Court.- Broadrick
- v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S., at 610; Brockett v. Spokane
- Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S., at 503-504. A defendant being
- prosecuted for speech or expressive conduct may challenge
- the law on its face if it reaches protected expression, even
- when that person's activities are not protected by the First
- Amendment. This is because -the possible harm to society
- in permitting some unprotected speech to go unpunished is
- outweighed by the possibility that protected speech of
- others may be muted.- Broadrick, supra, at 612; Osborne
- v. Ohio, 495 U. S., at 112, n. 8; New York v. Ferber, supra,
- at 768-769; Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Environ-
- ment, 444 U. S. 620, 634 (1980); Gooding v. Wilson, 405
- U. S. 518, 521 (1972).
- However, we have consistently held that, because over-
- breadth analysis is -strong medicine,- it may be invoked to
- strike an entire statute only when the overbreadth of the
- statute is not only -real, but substantial as well, judged in
- relation to the statute's plainly legitimate sweep,- Broad-
- rick, 413 U. S., at 615, and when the statute is not suscepti-
- ble to limitation or partial invalidation. Id., at 613; Board
- of Airport Comm'rs of Los Angeles v. Jews for Jesus, Inc.,
- 482 U. S. 569, 574 (1987). -When a federal court is dealing
- with a federal statute challenged as overbroad, it should . . .
- construe the statute to avoid constitutional problems, if the
- statute is subject to a limiting construction.- Ferber, 458
- U. S., at 769, n. 24. Of course, -[a] state court is also free
- to deal with a state statute in the same way.- Ibid. See,
- e.g., Osborne, 495 U. S. at 113-114.
- Petitioner contends that the St. Paul ordinance is not
- susceptible to a narrowing construction and that the
- ordinance therefore should be considered as written, and
- not as construed by the Minnesota Supreme Court.
- Petitioner is wrong. Where a state court has interpreted a
- provision of state law, we cannot ignore that interpretation,
- even if it is not one that we would have reached if we were
- construing the statute in the first instance. Ibid.; Kolender
- v. Lawson, 461 U. S. 352, 355 (1983); Hoffman Estates v.
- Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U. S. 489, 494, n. 5
- (1982).
- Of course, the mere presence of a state court interpreta-
- tion does not insulate a statute from overbreadth review.
- We have stricken legislation when the construction supplied
- by the state court failed to cure the overbreadth problem.
- See, e.g., Lewis v. City of New Orleans, 415 U. S. 130,
- 132-133 (1974); Gooding, supra, at 524-525. But in such
- cases, we have looked to the statute as construed in
- determining whether it contravened the First Amendment.
- Here, the Minnesota Supreme Court has provided an
- authoritative construction of the St. Paul antibias ordi-
- nance. Consideration of petitioner's overbreadth claim
- must be based on that interpretation.
- I agree with petitioner that the ordinance is invalid on its
- face. Although the ordinance as construed reaches catego-
- ries of speech that are constitutionally unprotected, it also
- criminalizes a substantial amount of expression that-how-
- ever repugnant-is shielded by the First Amendment.
- In attempting to narrow the scope of the St. Paul antibias
- ordinance, the Minnesota Supreme Court relied upon two
- of the categories of speech and expressive conduct that fall
- outside the First Amendment's protective sphere: words
- that incite -imminent lawless action,- Brandenburg v. Ohio,
- 395 U. S. 444, 449 (1969), and -fighting- words, Chaplinsky
- v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S., at 571-572. The Minnesota
- Supreme Court erred in its application of the Chaplinsky
- fighting words test and consequently interpreted the St.
- Paul ordinance in a fashion that rendered the ordinance
- facially overbroad.
- In construing the St. Paul ordinance, the Minnesota
- Supreme Court drew upon the definition of fighting words
- that appears in Chaplinsky-words -which by their very
- utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate
- breach of the peace.- Id., at 572. However, the Minnesota
- court was far from clear in identifying the -injur[ies]-
- inflicted by the expression that St. Paul sought to regulate.
- Indeed, the Minnesota court emphasized (tracking the
- language of the ordinance) that -the ordinance censors only
- those displays that one knows or should know will create
- anger, alarm or resentment based on racial, ethnic, gender
- or religious bias.- In re Welfare of R. A. V., 464 N.W. 2d
- 507, 510 (1991). I therefore understand the court to have
- ruled that St. Paul may constitutionally prohibit expression
- that -by its very utterance- causes -anger, alarm or resent-
- ment.-
- Our fighting words cases have made clear, however, that
- such generalized reactions are not sufficient to strip
- expression of its constitutional protection. The mere fact
- that expressive activity causes hurt feelings, offense, or
- resentment does not render the expression unprotected.
- See United States v. Eichman, 496 U. S. 310, 319 (1990);
- Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397, 409, 414 (1989); Hustler
- Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U. S. 46, 55-56 (1988); FCC
- v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726, 745 (1978); Hess v.
- Indiana, 414 U. S. 105, 107-108 (1973); Cohen v. Califor-
- nia, 403 U. S. 15, 20 (1971); Street v. New York, 394 U. S.
- 576, 592 (1969); Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 (1949).
- In the First Amendment context, -[c]riminal statutes
- must be scrutinized with particular care; those that make
- unlawful a substantial amount of constitutionally protected
- conduct may be held facially invalid even if they also have
- legitimate application.- Houston v. Hill, 482 U. S. 451, 459
- (1987) (citation omitted). The St. Paul antibias ordinance
- is such a law. Although the ordinance reaches conduct that
- is unprotected, it also makes criminal expressive conduct
- that causes only hurt feelings, offense, or resentment, and
- is protected by the First Amendment. Cf. Lewis, supra, at
- 132. The ordinance is therefore fatally overbroad and
- invalid on its face.
- III
- Today, the Court has disregarded two established
- principles of First Amendment law without providing a
- coherent replacement theory. Its decision is an arid,
- doctrinaire interpretation, driven by the frequently irresist-
- ible impulse of judges to tinker with the First Amendment.
- The decision is mischievous at best and will surely confuse
- the lower courts. I join the judgment, but not the folly of
- the opinion.
-